We've noticed a few things:
1) This is the only philosophy student blog in Manitoba.
2) Most of our posters/readers are not only interested in metaphysics.
3) Restricting this blog to a metaphysics-blog reinforces the false belief that there is a fundamental difference between metaphysicians and other philosophers.
How to solve this? Change this blog! Henceforth, this will be the Philosophy Student blog, where ALL philosophy students in Manitoba (the province, not just the university) will be allowed to post what they're working on.
There's not a lot rules. Keep it as brief as possible, keep it to one main idea per post. Make the argument as clear as you can. (If you're not allowed to post, contact the U of M facebook page and I'll make you a contributor).
Oh, and be nice! A lot of time on the blog will be spent on disagreements between people. If there is a post that I deem too aggressive, I reserve the right to delete it.
A blog for Manitoba philosophy students. All posts on all topics are welcome. Message the U of M Philosophy Students Association on Facebook if you want to become a poster.
Saturday, 30 November 2013
Thursday, 28 November 2013
M: If sentence S is a metaphor, then S has a metaphorical meaning based on the intention of the speaker.
Do you agree with M? If yes, you need to change your mind, why? Look:
1- consider the linguistic structure x is y
2- There is no metaphorical meaning associated with x is y.
2- There is no metaphorical meaning associated with x is y.
3- pick up two words randomly without any intentions, For instance, tree and sky and insert them in the structure.
4- The sentence sky is tree is a metaphor.
5- There is no metaphorical meaning based on the intention of the utterer for the sentence sky is tree (Because of the rule of random)
5- (4 and 5) is true.
6- so M is false
P.S. Don't try to reject 2 or 4
P.S. Don't try to reject 2 or 4
Thursday, 14 November 2013
I Could Have Failed to Be a Person
I could
have failed to be a person. There is a sense in which this claim is almost trivial.
Had I not existed, I would not have been a person. I say almost trivial for two
reasons. First, Kit Fine rejects the claim that: had I not
existed, I would not have been a person (Fine, 2005). Second, some
philosophers think that it is impossible for me to have failed to exist (see
Williamson, 2002; Linsky and Zalta, 1994). These philosophers, however, think that I could have been non-concrete (which I understand as non-physical), and had I been non-concrete, I would not have
been a person. So there is still a version of the argument above that is almost
trivial to them.
I want to look
at an argument for a stronger sense in which I could have failed to be a
person. More specifically, I want to claim:
(P) It is
possible for me to be a concrete object that is not a person.
My argument
for (P) is as follows:
(1) I used
to be an embryo.
(2)
Necessarily, no embryo is a person.
(3) Necessarily,
any embryo is a concrete object.
(4) So, I
used to be a concrete object that was not a person (1, 2, 3).
(P) So, it
is possible for me to be a concrete object that is not a person (4).
The
argument is valid. (P) follows from (4) by the plausible principle that everything
that has been the case is also possibly the case (I've toyed with the idea of denying this principle, but that will be left for another day). (4) follows from (1), (2) and
(3): Given (1), I was an embryo. Given (2), when I was an embryo, I was not a
person. Given (3), When I was an embryo and not a person, I was a concrete
object. So when I was an embryo, I was a concrete object that was not a person. Here is a
defense of (1)-(3), in reverse order:
Defense of
(3): In order for something to be an embryo, it must be located somewhere. But
only concrete objects are located. So in order for something to be an embryo,
it must be concrete. So necessarily, any embryo is a concrete object.
Defense of
(2): In order for something to be a person, it must have rights. Necessarily, no
embryos have rights. So, necessarily, no embryos are persons. Why think that no
embryos have rights? Embryos are physically not much different than fungi
(there are some differences, but not morally relevant ones). But necessarily, fungi
don’t have rights. So necessarily, embryos don’t have rights.
Defense of
(1): Here are two reasons for believing (1).
(i) Somewhere around March 1990, I was conceived. If I was conceived around
that time, then I had a property at that time (HAVING-BEEN-CONCEIVED, for example). If I had
a property at that time, then I existed at that time. So I existed at conception. 8 weeks
later, the only thing in my mother’s uterus which had existed at conception was
an embryo. So I used to be an embryo.
(ii) embryos are not essentially
embryos. Embryos used to be zygotes, and zygotes are not embryos. So there is
no reason to think, going the other way, that if something which is an embryo
stops being an embryo, it will go out of existence. The thing which used to be
an embryo in my mother’s uterus underwent several small changes, none of which would
have been enough to destroy it. It became a fetus, and stopped being an embryo, but that is also
not enough to destroy something, since embryos are not essentially embryos. Since fetuses are also not essentially fetuses, there is no reason to think that the fetus in my mother's uterus was destroyed when it underwent enough changes to no longer be a fetus. So
there is no reason to think that the thing which used to be an embryo in my mother's uterus was ever
destroyed. So there should be something around today which used to be an
embryo in my mother's uterus. It seems plausible that whatever used to be an embryo in my mother's uterus is going to be located
where I am. So either there is an ex-embryo coincident with me, or I used to be
an embryo. But there is no ex-embryo coincident with me. So I used to be an
embryo.
If my
defenses are good, then we should believe (P). But there is a problem with (P).
The following argument against (P) appears to be devastating:
(5) If I am
essentially a person, then it is not possible for me to be a concrete object that
is not a person.
(6) I am
essentially a person.
(7) So, it
is not possible for me to be a concrete object that is not a person.
The
argument is valid by modus ponens, and (7) is the denial of (P). Here is a
defense of the premises:
Defense of
(5): Assume I am essentially a person. Then necessarily, if I am concrete, I am
a person. But if necessarily, if I am concrete, I am a person, then it is
impossible for me to be a concrete object that is not a person. So, under the
assumption that I am essentially a person, it is impossible for me to be a
concrete object that is not a person. So, if I am essentially a person, then it
is not possible for me to be a concrete object that is not a person
Defense of
(6): It would seem that it is in my nature to be a person; I am the kind of
thing that is a must be a person. But if it is in my nature to be a person,
then I am essentially a person. So, I am essentially a person.
I’m
thinking of denying (5), but before I do, I thought I’d leave what I’ve already
written for discussion. Tune in next week, where I take the single most
plausible statement in this entire write-up and try to argue against it.
References:
Fine, Kit. 2005. "Necessity and Non-Existence," in Modality and Tense, New York: Oxford. 321-354
Linski, Bernard and Zalta, Edward. 1994. “In Defense of the Simplest Quantified Modal Logic” Philosophical Perspectives, 8: 431-458
Linski, Bernard and Zalta, Edward. 1994. “In Defense of the Simplest Quantified Modal Logic” Philosophical Perspectives, 8: 431-458
Williamson,
Timothy. 2002. “Necessary Existents.” in A. O’Hear, ed., Logic, Thought and Language,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 233-251
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)